Part 1 (1/2)
Some Remarks on the Tragedy of Hamlet, Prince of Denmark.
Written by Mr. William Shakespeare (1736).
by Anonymous.
INTRODUCTION
The ident.i.ty of the ”Anonymous” of _Some Remarks on Hamlet Prince of Denmark_ has never been established. The tradition that Hanmer wrote the essay had its highly dubious origin in a single unsupported statement by Sir Henry Bunbury, made over one hundred years after the work was written, in his _Correspondence of Sir Thomas Hanmer, with a Memoir of His Life_ (London, 1838), to the effect that he had reason to believe that Hanmer was the author. The evidence against this bare surmise is such, however, as to compel a.s.sent to Professor Lounsbury's judgment that Hanmer's authors.h.i.+p ”is so improbable that it may be called impossible” (_Shakespeare as a Dramatic Artist_, 60). I have elsewhere set down reasons for my own belief that Hanmer could have had nothing to do with the composition of the essay, arguing on grounds of ideas, att.i.tudes, style, and other internal evidence (”Thomas Hanmer and the Anonymous Essay on _Hamlet_,” _MLN_61 [1934], 493-498). Without going over the case again, I wish here merely to reaffirm my conviction that Hanmer was not the author, and to say that it would seem that the difference in styles and the att.i.tude of Anonymous toward Pope and Theobald are alone convincing proof that Hanmer had no part in the _Remarks_. Hanmer's style is stiff, formal, pedantic; the style of the essay is free, easy, direct, more in the Addison manner. Hanmer was a disciple of Pope's, and in his Preface to his Shakespeare and in his edition as a whole shows allegiance to Pope. Anonymous, on the contrary, decisively, though urbanely, rejects Pope's edition in favor of Theobald's text and notes. The fact that Theobald was at that time still the king of dunces in the _Dunciad_, adds to the improbability that an admirer of Pope's, as Hanmer certainly was, would pay Theobald such honor.
Most careful scholars of our day go no further on the question of authors.h.i.+p than to note that the essay has been ”attributed” to Hanmer; some, like Professor Stoll, seem to have dropped the idea that Hanmer was in any way connected with it and safely speak of ”the author” or ”the anonymous author”; I recall only one case in recent years of an all-out, incautious a.s.signment of the authors.h.i.+p to Hanmer (”Hamlet among the Mechanists,” _Shakespeare a.s.sociation Bulletin_ 17 [July, 1942], 138). It would seem advisable to follow Stoll's lead and ignore Hanmer entirely.
The anonymous essay has been of continued interest to students of Shakespeare. Echoes of its ideas if not its words appear in such later critics of the eighteenth century as Gentleman, Steevens, Richardson, and Morgann; in 1790 Malone copied out some two pages of the best of it for publication; and in 1864 the whole was reprinted, a not too usual thing for an obscure eighteenth century pamphlet. Present-day students of Shakespeare, among them D.N. Smith, Lounsbury, Babc.o.c.k, Lawrence, and Stoll have treated the essay with unvarying respect. Remarking that it antic.i.p.ates some of Johnson's arguments, Smith calls it in general a ”well-written, interesting book” greatly superior to the anonymous essay on Hamlet of 1752 (_Eighteenth Century Essays on Shakespeare_, xxn).
Lawrence has recently praised a selected pa.s.sage for its ”wise words ...
which may be pondered with profit” (Hamlet and Fortinbras, _PMLA_61 [1946], 697). And Stoll, who has obviously read the book with care, has found in one of its statements the very ”beginning of historical criticism” (PQ 24 [1945], 291; _Shakespeare Studies_, 212n.), and has elsewhere seen much to commend in it.
Reasons for such attention are not difficult to find; for the _Remarks_ is both intrinsically and historically an important piece of criticism.
It is still worth reading for more than one pa.s.sage of discerning a.n.a.lysis and apt comment on scene, speech, or character, and for certain not unfruitful excursions into the field of general aesthetics; while historically it is a sort of landmark in Shakespearian literature.
Standing chronologically almost midway between Dryden and Johnson, Kames, and Richardson, the _Remarks_ shows decisively the direction in which criticism, under the steadily mounting pressure of liberal, empirical thought, is traveling. This little unpretentious book gathers into itself, either in faint adumbration or in fairly advanced form, the tendencies in method and ideas that are to remake criticism in the eighteenth century. There are reflected here the growing distrust of the ”Rules” and the deepening faith in mind as the measure and in imagination as the instrument. There is also added recognition of the integrity of effects as a factor in judging literature.
Anonymous is an earlier member of the School of Taste. He is none-the-less concerned with firm principles by which to justify his acceptances and rejections. His announced over-all rule is conformity to ”Reason and Nature”--old words that he uses in the newer way. But he is also handily equipped with a stock of stubbornly conservative principles, reaching at times the status of bias, that serve to hold his taste in balance and effectively check unrestrained admiration.
This conservative side of Anonymous must not pa.s.s unnoticed, for it is the part of him that most closely identifies him with his forebears and so throws his more original, independent side into stronger relief. Our author is, not unexpectedly, an invariable moralist; is throughout a stickler for dignity; is sensitive to absurdities, improprieties, and slips in decorum; will have no truck with tragi-comedy in any of its forms. He hates puns and bombast, demands refinement in speech and restraint in manners. He regards Hamlet's speeches to Ophelia in the Player scene as a violation of propriety, is shocked by the lack of decency in the representation of Ophelia's madness, finds Hamlet's frequent levity and the buffoonery of Polonius alike regrettable --Shakespeare's favorite foible, he feels, is ”that of raising a laugh.”
The introduction of Fortinbras and his army on the stage is ”an Absurdity”; the grave-diggers' scene is ”very unbecoming to tragedy”; the satire on the ”Children of the Chapel” is not allowable in this kind of piece.
In all these things Anonymous is an upholder of the tradition of true, restrained wit. But unlike some of his contemporaries, he has a formula for discounting faults. ”But we should be very cautious in finding Fault with Men of such exalted Genius as our Author certainly was, lest we should blame them when in reality the Fault lies in our own slow Conceptions ...” This is the language of tolerance, a tolerance that can overlook faults for the sake of greater beauties--one of the distinct marks of the new criticism to which the _Remarks_ belongs.
The essay starts out in a boldly challenging tone. Criticism, says the author, has been badly abused: it has been regarded as an excuse for the ill-natured to find fault or for the better-natured to eulogize. But true criticism has for its end ”to set in the best light all Beauties, and to touch upon Defects no more than is necessary.” Beyond this it seeks to set up a right taste for the age. His own purpose is to examine a great tragedy ”according to the Rules of Reason and Nature, without having any regard to those Rules established by arbitrary Dogmatizing Critics ...” More specifically, he proposes to show the why of our pleasure in this piece: ”And as to those things which charm by a certain secret Force, and strike us we know not how, or why; I believe it will not be disagreeable, if I shew to everyone the Reason why they are pleas'd ...” This, it need hardly be observed, is all pretty much in the vein of Addison, whom the author extols and whose papers on _Paradise Lost_, he tells us, have furnished a model for the present undertaking. Throughout his criticism Addison had deprecated mere fault-finding and had urged the positive approach of emphasis on beauties. In the last twelve essays on Milton's poem he had shown a new way in critical writing, the way of particular as opposed to general criticism, with the selection of specific details for praise and explication; in his essay on the Imagination he had sought to find a rationale for that kind of criticism: in which a man of true taste, going beyond the mechanical rules, ”would enter into the very Spirit and Soul of Fine Writing, and shew us the several Sources of that Pleasure which rises in the Mind upon the Perusal of a n.o.ble Work.” With such ideas in mind, Anonymous proceeds to study _Hamlet_, in what is probably the first act-by-act, scene-by-scene a.n.a.lysis of a play in English, according to his understanding of the principles of the ”new criticism”
as he finds them ill.u.s.trated in Addison's theory and practice.
Having brushed aside the ”fantastick Rules” of the conventional critics, he proceeds to apply his laws of ”Reason and Nature” as criteria by which to test the validity of Shakespeare's effects and to discover the cause of these effects. The results he achieves are in part conditioned by his interpretation of his basic terms. Reason and Nature had been invoked by many previous critics; but to Anonymous these words are not what they were to Boileau and Pope. They particularly have nothing, or next to nothing, to do with the Deistic concept of a universal nature of external diversity but of an internal rational and universal order, which art reveals and to which art at its best conforms. To Anonymous, who in this is following the lead of the Hobbian school, the nature that is the norm by which Shakespeare is to be judged is merely human nature, used as Whately, Richardson, and Morgann are to use it later, and as Johnson uses it when he argues that there is an appeal open from custom to nature. Anonymous' interest is in the way the mind works and the way people customarily act. So also when he talks about reason, he is thinking only of what is acceptable to a logical, healthy mind. He has no thought of identifying nature or reason with the traditional Rules or with Homer. On the contrary, he is willing to set both of them quite apart from, or even in opposition to the Rules (with a qualifying concession that they may sometimes meet), and he definitely renounces obligation to show that Shakespeare bears any relation to the ancients whatever, denying at the same time the value of the customary shows of learning in discussing his work. For Shakespeare apparently drew little from the authors of antiquity: ”Nature was our great Poet's Mistress; her alone has he followed as his Conductress.”
Such a view is emanc.i.p.atory. Free the critic from the idea that nature and the ancients are the same and that reason and the laws ascribed to the ancients are identical, and he is ready to look at modern literature with an independent judgment and to see what it is like and what it is worth in and by itself. Release the critic from the necessity of regarding nature as universal order and reason as the directive of this order, and, whatever the loss in philosophic concept, he is ready for a more specific and particular investigation that turns its attention to basic human behavior and the basic ways of the mind as the criterion by which to judge artistic representation. No need now for quaint parallels with the ancients to justify modern practice, nor for scholarly arguments to prove learning; all that is required is to prove adherence to common nature and common rationality. This is the ground upon which Anonymous stands, and it is the ground upon which Morgann is to stand when he gives us the ”Falstaff of Nature,” and Johnson when he presents Shakespeare as the dramatist who is ”above all modern writers the poet of nature,” whose ”persons act and speak by the influence of those general pa.s.sions by which all minds are agitated,” whose ”drama is the mirror of life,” in which his readers may find ”human sentiments in human language,” whose practices are to be judged not by appeal to the rules of criticism, but by reference to the author's design and the great law of nature and reason.
This position opens the way for further advances. Thus, beginning with the a.s.sumption that the mind of the spectator or the reader is the chief arbiter in such matters, Anonymous gives us what is perhaps the most enlightened comment on probability and illusion to be found in the period between Dryden and Coleridge. His test for probability is what the imagination will readily accept; and the imagination, he says, will bear a ”strong Imposition.” Reason, to be sure, demands that actions and speeches shall be ”natural”--but natural within the framework of the situation and character as established by the dramatist on the imaginative level. The author's words on illusion recall the pa.s.sage in Dryden about reason's suffering itself to be ”hoodwinked” by imaginative presentation, foreshadow Coleridge's ”willing suspension of disbelief,”
and directly suggest Johnson's pa.s.sages on the subject. Experience will show, he says, ”that no Dramatick Piece can affect us but by the Delusion of our Imagination; which, to taste true and real Pleasures at such Representations, must undergo a very great Imposition.” For example, on our stage all nations speak English, and shock no one; also the actors are recognized as actors and not as the persons represented, and the stage as a stage and not Rome, or Denmark. Without such imposition ”farewell all Dramatick Performances.”
And then, in continuation of this pre-Johnsonian (and pre-Coleridgean) argument he goes on to say that delusion must be accepted, never, however, in defiance of our reason but with the approval of our reason.
That Shakespeare's plays create delusion with the a.s.sistance of reason is proved by the success they have so long enjoyed. Sublimity of sentiments, exalted diction, and ”in short all the Charms of his Poetry, far outweigh any little absurdities in his Plots.” He knew how to work up ”great and moving Circ.u.mstances in such a Way as to affect our Pa.s.sions strongly.” The word used here throughout is _delusion_, but the sense, just as is largely the case with Johnson, is _illusion_--not a demand for such a verisimilitude as will deceive, but for such representation as will lead the imagination to voluntary, pleasurable acceptance.
Likewise, when Anonymous considers unity his emphasis, like Johnson's and Hurd's, is no longer on the mechanical unities but on unity of design. ”When Shakespeare's plan is understood most of the criticisms of Rymer and Voltaire vanish away,” Johnson was to write some thirty years later. Anonymous holds steadily for the integrity of Shakespeare's plan in Hamlet. Of Act I, iii he says, ”Concerning the Design of this scene, we shall find it is necessary towards the whole plot of the Play”; he speaks of I, iv as an ”important Scene, on which turns the Whole Play”; the killing of Polonious, he explains, ”was in Conformity to the Plan _Shakespeare_ built his Play upon”; and finally, of the piece as a whole, he a.s.serts that ”there is not one Scene but what some way or other conduces toward the _Denoument_ of the Whole; and thus the Unity of Action is indisputably kept up by everything tending to what we may call the main Design, and it all hangs by Consequence so close together, that no Scene can be omitted, without Prejudice to the Whole.” When one recalls that the idea of unity of design as evolved in Thomas Warton, Hurd, and Johnson was the intermediate step on the way to a full theory of organic unity we see the importance of such pa.s.sages in the forward march of criticism.
There is in the _Remarks_ a closer examination of event and character than is usual in the period, again in the light of what it reasonable and natural. The includes some ”psychologizing” of persons in the play, specifically in partial a.n.a.lyses of Laertes, Polonious, and Hamlet, enough to foreshadow the later vogue but none of it very remarkable.