Part 16 (2/2)

Hence the three ages were, at first, _x_, 2_x_, 3_x_; and the number of years, since that time is two-thirds of 6_x_, _i.e._ is 4_x_. Hence the present ages are 5_x_, 6_x_, 7_x_. The ages are clearly _integers_, since this is only ”the year when one of my sons comes of age.” Hence 7_x_ = 21, _x_ = 3, and the other ages are 15, 18.

Eighteen answers have been received. One of the writers merely a.s.serts that the first occasion was 12 years ago, that the ages were then 9, 6, and 3; and that on the second occasion they were 14, 11, and 8! As a Roman father, I _ought_ to withhold the name of the rash writer; but respect for age makes me break the rule: it is THREE SCORE AND TEN. JANE E. also a.s.serts that the ages at first were 9, 6, 3: then she calculates the present ages, leaving the _second_ occasion unnoticed. OLD HEN is nearly as bad; she ”tried various numbers till I found one that fitted _all_ the conditions”; but merely scratching up the earth, and pecking about, is _not_ the way to solve a problem, oh venerable bird! And close after OLD HEN prowls, with hungry eyes, OLD CAT, who calmly a.s.sumes, to begin with, that the son who comes of age is the _eldest_. Eat your bird, Puss, for you will get nothing from me!

There are yet two zeroes to dispose of. MINERVA a.s.sumes that, on _every_ occasion, a son comes of age; and that it is only such a son who is ”tipped with gold.” Is it wise thus to interpret ”now, my boys, calculate your ages, and you shall have the money”? BRADSHAW OF THE FUTURE says ”let” the ages at first be 9, 6, 3, then a.s.sumes that the second occasion was 6 years afterwards, and on these baseless a.s.sumptions brings out the right answers. Guide _future_ travellers, an thou wilt: thou art no Bradshaw for _this_ Age!

Of those who win honours, the merely ”honourable” are two. DINAH MITE ascertains (rightly) the relations.h.i.+p between the three ages at first, but then _a.s.sumes_ one of them to be ”6,” thus making the rest of her solution tentative. M. F. C. does the algebra all right up to the conclusion that the present ages are 5_z_, 6_z_, and 7_z_; it then a.s.sumes, without giving any reason, that 7_z_ = 21.

Of the more honourable, DELTA attempts a novelty--to discover _which_ son comes of age by elimination: it a.s.sumes, successively, that it is the middle one, and that it is the youngest; and in each case it _apparently_ brings out an absurdity. Still, as the proof contains the following bit of algebra, ”63 = 7_x_ + 4_y_; [** therefore] 21 = _x_ + 4 sevenths of _y_,” I trust it will admit that its proof is not _quite_ conclusive. The rest of its work is good. MAGPIE betrays the deplorable tendency of her tribe--to appropriate any stray conclusion she comes across, without having any _strict_ logical right to it. a.s.suming _A_, _B_, _C_, as the ages at first, and _D_ as the number of the years that have elapsed since then, she finds (rightly) the 3 equations, 2_A_ = _B_, _C_ = _B_ + _A_, _D_ = 2_B_. She then says ”supposing that _A_ = 1, then _B_ = 2, _C_ = 3, and _D_ = 4. Therefore for _A_, _B_, _C_, _D_, four numbers are wanted which shall be to each other as 1:2:3:4.” It is in the ”therefore” that I detect the unconscientiousness of this bird.

The conclusion _is_ true, but this is only because the equations are ”h.o.m.ogeneous” (_i.e._ having one ”unknown” in each term), a fact which I strongly suspect had not been grasped--I beg pardon, clawed--by her.

Were I to lay this little pitfall, ”_A_ + 1 = _B_, _B_ + 1 = _C_; supposing _A_ = 1, then _B_ = 2 and _C_ = 3. _Therefore_ for _A_, _B_, _C_, three numbers are wanted which shall be to one another as 1:2:3,”

would you not flutter down into it, oh MAGPIE, as amiably as a Dove?

SIMPLE SUSAN is anything but simple to _me_. After ascertaining that the 3 ages at first are as 3:2:1, she says ”then, as two-thirds of their sum, added to one of them, = 21, the sum cannot exceed 30, and consequently the highest cannot exceed 15.” I suppose her (mental) argument is something like this:--”two-thirds of sum, + one age, = 21; [** therefore] sum, + 3 halves of one age, = 31 and a half. But 3 halves of one age cannot be less than 1 and-a-half (here I perceive that SIMPLE SUSAN would on no account present a guinea to a new-born baby!) hence the sum cannot exceed 30.” This is ingenious, but her proof, after that, is (as she candidly admits) ”clumsy and roundabout.” She finds that there are 5 possible sets of ages, and eliminates four of them. Suppose that, instead of 5, there had been 5 million possible sets? Would SIMPLE SUSAN have courageously ordered in the necessary gallon of ink and ream of paper?

The solution sent in by C. R. is, like that of SIMPLE SUSAN, partly tentative, and so does not rise higher than being Clumsily Right.

Among those who have earned the highest honours, ALGERNON BRAY solves the problem quite correctly, but adds that there is nothing to exclude the supposition that all the ages were _fractional_. This would make the number of answers infinite. Let me meekly protest that I _never_ intended my readers to devote the rest of their lives to writing out answers! E. M. RIX points out that, if fractional ages be admissible, any one of the three sons might be the one ”come of age”; but she rightly rejects this supposition on the ground that it would make the problem indeterminate. WHITE SUGAR is the only one who has detected an oversight of mine: I had forgotten the possibility (which of course ought to be allowed for) that the son, who came of age that _year_, need not have done so by that _day_, so that he _might_ be only 20. This gives a second solution, viz., 20, 24, 28. Well said, pure Crystal!

Verily, thy ”fair discourse hath been as sugar”!

CLa.s.s LIST.

I.

ALGERNON BRAY.

AN OLD FOGEY.

E. M. RIX.

G. S. C.

S. S. G.

TOKIO.

T. R.

WHITE SUGAR.

II.

C. R.

DELTA.

MAGPIE.

SIMPLE SUSAN.

III.

DINAH MITE.

M. F. C.

<script>